Scientific Philosophy

Induction: Possibilities, frequency, and confidence

/
528 views

Miguel López-Astorga  
Institute of Humanistic Studies, Research Center on Cognitive Sciences, University of Talca, Talca Campus (Chile)

Rupkatha Journal, Vol. 15, Issue 4, 2023. https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v15n4.01
[Article History: Received: 22 August 2023. Revised: 18 October 2023. Accepted: 19 October 2023. Published: 20 October 2023]
Full-Text PDF Issue Access

Abstract

The theory of mental models describes how human beings often make inductive inferences. That account is based on possibilities. It claims that, in inductions, people tend to prefer the possibility that seems to be more probable. The present paper tries to develop the account by proposing an additional quantitative method to determine which of the two possibilities in inductive processes is preferable. The paper resorts to a Non-Axiomatic Logic: NAL. NAL assigns quantitative values to the frequency and confidence of sentences. It also shows how those values can be transmitted from premises to conclusions in inductive inferences. This part of NAL is applied to the account of induction the theory of mental models gives.

Keywords: confidence, frequency, induction, mental models, non-axiomatic logic.

Sustainable Development Goals: Quality Education
Citation: López-Astorga, Miguel. 2023. Induction: Possibilities, frequency, and confidence. Rupkatha Journal 15:4. https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v15n4.01 

On the Perceptibility of Motion: An Inquiry from the Indian Philosophical Traditions

/
537 views

1Manoj Bhandari &2Shruti Krishna Bhat &3Vishwanath Dhital
1Department of Humanistic Studies, IIT (BHU), Varanasi.
2Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay.
3Department of Humanistic Studies, IIT (BHU), Varanasi.

Rupkatha Journal, Vol. 15, Issue 3, 2023. https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v15n3.04
[Article History: Received: 17 June 2023. Revised: 09 August 2023. Accepted: 09 August 2023. Published: 15 August 2023.]
Full-Text PDF  Issue Access

Abstract

This paper discusses an important issue regarding the concept of motion from the perspective of Indian philosophical traditions. We can recognise two camps in Indian philosophical schools regarding the epistemic means (pramana) through which one cognises motion. Some Indian philosophical schools claim that motion is completely imperceptible and one infers motion by perceiving contact and separation of an object with another object or space. Among these schools, we have considered Patanjali and Ramanuja (the author of Tantrarahasya) as the main advocators of this position. The other group claims that motion is perceptible and we infer motion only when the object possessing the motion is not perceptible. Supporters of this position are mainly the Nyaya-Vaisesika school and Narayanabhatta the author of Manameyodaya.  While summarising and critically analysing these positions, we support the view that motion is perceptible by showing the following: (1) The position that motion is non-perceptible leads to some ontological issues (2) The position that motion is perceptible is more economical and simpler.

Keywords: motion, perception, inference, Nyaya-Vaisasika, Vyakarana, Mimamsa
[Sustainable Development Goals: Quality Education]
Citation: Bhandari, Manoj, Shruti Krishna Bhat, Vishwanath Dhital. 2023. On the Perceptibility of Motion: An Inquiry from the Indian Philosophical Traditions. Rupkatha Journal 15:3. https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v15n3.04 

Logic as a Tool for Developing Critical Thinking

/
432 views

Lukas Vartiak1, Galina Jaseckova2, Milan Konvit3

1Comenius University, Faculty of Social and Economic Sciences, Institute of Mediamatics, Bratislava, Slovakia. ORCID: 0000-0002-9735-5945. Email: lukas.vartiak@fses.uniba.sk

2Comenius University, Faculty of Social and Economic Sciences, Institute of Mediamatics, Bratislava, Slovakia. ORCID: 0000-0002-3699-8082. Email: galina.jaseckova@fses.uniba.sk

3Comenius University, Faculty of Social and Economic Sciences, Institute of Mediamatics, Bratislava, Slovakia. ORCID: 0000-0002-4959-7819. Email: milan.konvit@fses.uniba.sk

[Received 25 May 20023, modified 26 June 2023, accepted 28 June 2023, first published 30 June 2023]

Rupkatha Journal, Vol. 15, Issue 2, June 2023. https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v15n2.15
Full-Text PDF Issue Access

Abstract

A characteristic feature of modern society is the ever-expanding information space. Hidden information attacks harm the lives of individuals and society in general. In this regard, studies of critical thinking seem particularly important to us. Therefore, critical thinking is interpreted in the academic discourse mainly in connection with the effort to cope with the growing amount of misinformation and hate speech. While teachers and policymakers consider critical thinking an important educational goal, many are unclear about developing this competency in a school setting. For many key competencies, the question is whether and how they can be acquired through planned educational courses/programs. Although there are specific training programs for critical thinking as a core competency, their design and effectiveness are scientifically controversial. Instruction in critical thinking becomes extremely important because it allows individuals to gain a more comprehensive understanding of the information they encounter and promotes good decision-making and problem-solving in real-world applications. Despite the ambiguity of the term critical thinking, its close connection with logical culture is evident. Logical culture is the culture of thinking manifested in the culture of written and oral speech. The starting point for developing critical thinking skills should be logic. Logic as a science of correct thinking is the basis on which the program for developing critical thinking is based. The paper’s main aim is to identify the status of critical thinking as an independent discipline. A partial aim of the paper is to define the relationship between critical thinking and logic. The paper is divided into six parts, while the main findings are summarised in conclusions. In its purest form, logic does not teach how to work with a changing context or apply it to the subject realities of various disciplines, but such characteristics as precision, clarity, provability, and persuasiveness are key for this science. It is through logic that the basic principles of thinking, which we call critical, are revealed, the rules of argumentation and definitions are explained, and misconceptions and errors are displayed. Logic is distinguished from other sciences by the fundamentality of the discussed problems. Logic is the only science that combines mathematics, computer science and humanities education. We believe that modern logic is only the beginning of the first of the sciences of a new generation, which will be invited to combine the analyticity of the scientific method with the synthetics of perception of the humanitarian point of view. Therefore, we believe that the development of critical thinking skills appears to be productive in combination with the study of logic and is a priority in the modern educational process. It is difficult to imagine the formation of critical thinking in isolation from the building of the logical culture of the individual, which gives him a solid foundation for understanding the essence of critical thinking.

Keywords: Logic, Informal logic, Critical thinking, Cognitive theories, Teaching Logic, Competencies.

Severe Acute Hepatitis in Children: An Analysis from Philosophy of Science Using the Concept of Reduction

//
401 views

Miguel López-Astorga
Institute of Humanistic Studies, University of Talca, Talca Campus (Chile). Email: milopez@utalca.cl.

Rupkatha Journal, Vol. 14, Issue 2, April-June, 2022, Pages 1-9.  https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v14n2.30

First published: June 30, 2022 | Area: Scientific Philosophy | License: CC BY-NC 4.0

(This article is published under Volume 14, Number 2, 2022)
Extract Full-Text PDF Cite
PlumX Metrics

Abstract

The present paper uses Carnap’s reduction concept to address the problem of new severe acute hepatitis in children. First, it tries to show how that concept can help understand why some previous hypotheses of causality on the new hepatitis in children should be rejected. Second, Carnap’s reduction concept is used to explain a complex hypothesis about the causes of that disease proposed in The Lancet in 2022. The latter hypothesis combines several factors: infection by SARS-CoV-2, a build-up of this virus in the bowel that comes in contact with blood circulation, and another infection by adenovirus. One of the points of the paper is to argue that a hypothesis can be described by means of a bilateral reduction sentence, which in turn would allow empirical comparison of the hypothesis in an easy way. Finally, the author considers a current cognitive framework, namely, the theory of mental models, to propose that bilateral reduction sentences should not be hard to handle for physicians or scientists.

Keywords: adenovirus; reduction; SARS-CoV-2; severe acute hepatitis in children; theory of mental models

Introduction

Several cases of a new ‘severe acute hepatitis in children were reported around the world in 2022 (e.g., Brodin & Arditi, 2022). Physicians and researchers tried to find, by all means, an explanation and the causes of those cases (see also, e.g., Cañelles, 2022). In the process, some hypotheses were ruled out. Some of them were, for example, to deem the new hepatitis as a disease equivalent to one of the five kinds of hepatitis already known, or an adenovirus (Brodin & Artidi, 2022; Cañelles, 2022).

After rejecting other hypotheses as well, one more hypothesis was proposed. This new hypothesis, in principle, seemed difficult to verify. It claimed that several elements acting at the same time cause the severe acute hepatitis in children. The new hepatitis would appear when there is a SARS-CoV-2 infection and, as a result, the virus accumulates in the intestine. Then, the virus would enter the blood and flow throughout the body. At once, the liver would be inflamed because of an adenovirus infection (Brodin & Artidi, 2022; Cañelles, 2022).

This hypothesis appears to be hard to contrast. However, the main goal of the present paper is to show otherwise. If the procedure Carnap (1936, 1937) offered to relate properties or predicates, that is, his reduction process is assumed, the task of empirical confirmation may not be so difficult. The literature reveals that, if it is accepted that the human mind follows, in its inferential processes, what the theory of mental models (e.g., Khemlani, Byrne, & Johnson-Laird, 2018) indicates, that procedure is not difficult at all (e.g., López-Astorga, 2021).

To achieve that goal, the present paper will have three sections. In the first section, some of the previous hypotheses about the causes of the new hepatitis in children will be taken as examples. The aim will be to explain how Carnap’s reduction processes can help reveal the reasons why those hypotheses are not admissible. The second section will describe the complex hypothesis pointed out above. It will be argued that, despite what may be thought, Carnap’s concept of reduction can lead to simple confirmations of that hypothesis. Based on the literature, the final section will show that to apply Carnap’s reduction procedure to that hypothesis is not hard for people, at least, if the theses of the theory of mental models are right… Full-Text PDF

The Construction of Performative Identities in Patriarchal Religious Institutions: A Study of Annie Besant’s An Autobiography with Special Reference to “Atheism as I Knew and Taught it”

//
784 views

Tanu Gupta

Professor, Department of English. Chandigarh University, Mohali, Punjab, India. ORCID id: 0000-0002-6969-5504. Email: tanu.e9349@cumail.in

Rupkatha Journal, Vol. 14, Issue 2, April-June, 2022, Pages  https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v14n2.22

First published: June 26, 2022 | Area: Gender Studies  | License: CC BY-NC 4.0

(This article is published under Volume 14, Number 2, 2022)
Full-Text HTML Full-Text PDF Cite
PlumX Metrics

Abstract

Annie Besant was a Victorian radical whose outspoken views included advocacy of women’s rights and atheism. In her mid-forties she went to live in India. Her An Autobiography (1893) charts her dramatic political and ethical awakenings, up to the point where she joined the Theosophical movement. It describes how she was unhappily married to a clergyman, contemplated suicide, embraced atheism, and legally separated from her husband. The present paper is an attempt to explore Annie Besant’s rebellion against patriarchal and religious institutions through an in-depth study of her autobiography with special reference to the chapter “Atheism as I Knew and Taught It”. The paper will analyze how Annie Besant revolted against the performative construction of identity which is the result of the patriarchal religious discourses, and how breaking the binary of theist/atheist gave her strength to further deconstruct the male/female binary.

Keywords: atheism, free thought, gender roles, women liberation, performativity, discourses, patriarchy, religion

  1. Introduction:

Nonconformity to religion results in proclivity for free thought i.e. a commitment to question everything and to give priority to the reason above all. The same nonconformity gives strength to the idea that gender differences are the product of social and cultural discourses. The present paper based on the study of Annie Besant’s “Atheism: As I Knew and Taught It”, taken from her autobiography, is an attempt to explore her rational and radical opinions about religious teachings and their impact on developing a sense of rebellion against all patriarchal institutions. The analysis is done by applying the views and results of Judith Bultler’s notion of performativity and Michel Foucault’s idea of normalization of power.

  1. Annie Besant’s Conversions:

Annie Besant wrote An Autobiography after her conversion into Theosophy which is a spiritualist philosophy influenced by Eastern religion. She is a woman who lived multiple lives—First, as a devout Christian who married a clergyman, then refused to take communion at church, eventually resulting in her legal separation, converted into “a free thinker, then a scientific materialist, then an atheist, finally into the most prominent female advocate for secularism and a woman activist” (Miller, 2009, p. 248). She emigrated to India in 1898, and became the first woman President of Indian National Congress. Her multiplicity of self as represented in her autobiography seems to be the result of her various conversions. Her shift from staunch Christian to free thought to Theosophy to atheism to feminist individualism represent an ongoing search for identity and a rebel against the performative construction of identity. Thus, when people later attacked her atheism as negative, she replied that humans should live in accord with truth, not superstition: ‘it is an error,’ she explained, ‘to regard my truth as negative and barren, for all truth is positive and fruitful’. (Besant, 1877, p. 7)

  1. Construction of Performative Identities in Religious Institutions:

Atheists are the individuals who do not believe in the existence of God or gods. They “tend to be less nationalistic, less prejudiced, less racist, less authoritarian, less ethnocentric, and less dogmatic than religious individuals” (Stinson, 2013, p.40). According to Christine Overall, there are many reasons to support this argument that feminists should be atheists. She posited that feminists should be atheists because religion perpetuates gender inequity.

“Historically, women have been excluded from education, including religious and theological education; hence they have not been involved in shaping religions or theologies. Women have also been denied leadership positions as priests, ministers, rabbis, and imams and have had only a subordinate participation in the life of many religions.” (Overall, 2007, p.235)

The roles based on gender are further institutionalized through religious beliefs. Atheists, however, are somewhat free to support women’s independence and equality as is seen in Annie Besant’s proclamations. Though the argument that atheists support gender equality is still under debate, atheists can realize how gender is constructed in the garb of religious systems as in education, family and social system. According to Judith Butler:

“. . . we often describe ourselves as having identities as if those identities exist in the real world whereas, in fact, the phrases which refer to those identities create them. Identity talk is a performance in which its objects are conjured up as much as it is analysis of things that exist out there – and it’s just one of the performances in which gender identities are maintained.” (Butler, 2001, p.341)

Religion plays a major role in maintaining these identities. Annie Besant declaring herself outright an atheist advocated and voiced for women’s rights in India along with other social reformers. “Known as Red Annie, she was a militant atheist, socialist, and trade union organizer, as well as women’s rights advocate.” (Nancy, 1994, p.563). Chastity for women has always been considered of having the utmost importance in most of the religions of the world.  It is considered one of the human virtues. Holy Mary, because of her being pure and virgin, is considered a perfect woman.

“According to the teachings of Quran and the New Testament, chastity and avoiding infection of moral and sexual deviations have been considered as outstanding characteristics of believers in community for having Communal pathways to sustainable and health living; especially leaders and leadership authority have no stability without emancipation of lusts and desires. Importance of modesty; that is the state of controlling against lust, has been repeatedly mentioned in Quran.” (Moosavi, 2016)

Annie Besant in her fervor for atheism “glorified human passion, and regarded sexual intercourse as perfecting the union of heart and mind.” (Nancy, 1994, p.565) In the essay taken up for study she puts forward:

“Virtue is an indispensable part of all true and solid happiness…. But it is, after all, only reasonable that happiness should be the ultimate test of right and wrong . . .” (Besant, 2018, p. 96).

The relationship between being virtuous and being chaste is highly debatable as it has always led to a negotiable performative identity rather than a stable state of sexual virtue. At the same time the relation between chastity and social reputation is also more complex as in the case of Annie Besant. Though Annie Besant herself was convicted for obscenity along with Charles Bradlaugh during her controversial campaign against birth control, yet her public proclamations about human passions did not lead to that much of social disgrace as these got compensated through other performative means.

Annie propounded her belief in Hinduism also:

“You have not only the Vedas and the Upanishads showing a mighty intellect…You find the very foundation of modern science laid down as part of the Hindu philosophy.” (Pillai, 2017)

However,

“Neither Hinduism nor women are stable, unified categories with one specific meaning, for each comprises complex, sometimes even contradictory, realities.” (King, p.523)

Annie Besant could easily recognize how spoken discourses operate within each institution and performativity here becomes an important factor to influence the identities of both the individuals and organizations in order to maintain market position.

Annie Besant observed the condition of Indian women closely and decried their restricted lives. While questioning Indian patriarchal discourse, she stumped her radical causes. In her first public lecture, Besant openly debated on the issue of women’s emancipation. In the journal National Reformer, she has regularly expressed her feminist ideals.

“. . . men restrict women’s action to the home? I can understand that, in Eastern lands, where the husband rules his wives with despotic authority, and woman is but the plaything and the slave of man, woman’s sphere is the home, for the very simple reason that she cannot get outside it … Shut any living creature up, and its prison becomes its sphere.” (Besant, 1885, pp. 10, 12)  

Annie Besant who was a woman of dreams and was always willing to use new ideas in place of the old ones could easily grasp the complexities of the situation. Her unorthodox religious views and her inclination towards atheism made her believe:

“Never forget that life can only be nobly inspired and rightly lived if you take it bravely and gallantly, as a splendid adventure in which you are setting out into an unknown country, to meet many a joy, to find many a comrade, to win and lose many a battle.” (Qtd. in Lewis)

During her twenties, she started developing serious doubts about her religious beliefs and eventually, she became anti-Church. She lost her faith in Christianity so much so that she refused to attend communion. She even got legally separated from her husband who used to order her to follow Christianity.

“I resolved to take Christianity as it had been taught in the Churches, and carefully and thoroughly examine its dogmas one by one, so that I should never again say “I believe” where I had not proved, and that, however diminished my area of belief, what was left of it might at least be firm under my feet. . . . that I lost all faith in Christianity.” (Besant, 2018, pp 58-59)

She got notoriety when she along with Charles Bradlaugh published Charles Knowlton’s ‘Fruits of Philosophy’, a pamphlet that advocated birth control. Her husband, Frank Besant, who was a clergyman and had always believed in the notion of husband’s authority and the wife’s submission.

“It is not your duty to ascertain the truth,” he told me, sternly. “It is your duty to accept and believe the truth as laid down by the Church. At your peril you reject it” (Besant, 2018, p. 67)

He even appointed a detective to see if she was sleeping with Charles Bradlaugh. Annie always revolted against the conditions imposed upon her. Rebelling against her marriage and being against the denial of a woman’s independence, she left her so-called religious husband and the secure life at home and ventured on a new path carving a niche for herself. For Foucault, the subject is constructed not only in language, as Lacan would have it, but through many different types of practices. Religion is one such practice through which power-knowledge effects are applied. Foucault rejected any notion of an essence of being, asserting that self and identities are constructed in particular contexts affected by non-discursive institutions, texts and discourses:

“. . . discourse is not simply that which translates struggles or systems of domination, but is thing for which or by which there is struggle, discourse is the power which is to be seized.” (Foucault, 1970, pp 52-53)

Annie Besant, who began her life immersed in religiosity, got transformed into an atheist and championed women’s cause. When she embraced atheism, she was charged with obscenity.

“Contraception was used as the convenient excuse to expose atheists as obscene and immoral. With this justification, the defenders of the Christian state could send atheist propagators to prison.” (Conrad, 2009, 59)

She was called a deranged female too. She couldn’t join any of the women’s rights organizations because of her controversial reputation but wrote widely on women’s emancipation and gender equality.  Once free not only from Frank Besant, her husband, but also from her orthodox views, she challenged the whole of conventional thinking:

“Having demonstrated, as I hope to do, that the orthodox idea of God is unreasonable and absurd, we will endeavour to ascertain whether any idea of God, worthy to be called an idea, is attainable in the present state of our faculties.” (Besant, 2018, p.88)

Her atheism made her believe strongly in human brotherhood. Instead of having warmth in showing reverence to God, she found more warmth in helping the poor people and improving their lot. By being an atheist, she started developing feelings for the sad ones.

“. . . where the cry of ‘Atheist’ is raised there may we be sure that another step is being taken towards the redemption of humanity. The saviours of the world are too often howled at as Atheists, and then worshipped as Deities.” (Besant, 2018, p. 94)

Her atheism can be compared to Protestantism which was once considered as selfish and subversive of all order, leading to a dangerous kind of equality.  The idea of “free examination” propounded by Protestants was seen as encouraging a sinful form of individualism that invariably led to the disrespect for community and tradition. However, for Annie Besant, this idea of free thinking can brighten sadness, can reform abuses and can be helpful in establishing equal justice for rich and poor:

 “There is no warmth in brightening the lot of the sad, in reforming abuses, in establishing equal justice for rich and poor? You find warmth in the church, but none in the home? Warmth in imagining the cloud glories of heaven, but none in creating substantial glories on earth?”  (Besant, 2018, p.99)

She realized that priesthood had become a profession and religious rule a prize for ambition. Her protestant spirit is quite evident here.

This made her approach more logical and scientific and made her think about equality at all levels, including gender equality. She raises her voice against all political structures. She evolved a system in which emancipation of women will not be “self-defeating” (Butler 342). She spoke against creating the “gendered subjects”, having a differential axis of domination as nowhere in the autobiography she presumed to be masculine. Eventually, she proclaimed her vision of the world which has women who are liberated and free thinkers. When she denies the existence of spirit or soul, she at the same time refuses to believe in God and religiosity. According to her:

“. . . that there can be only one eternal and underived substance, and that matter and spirit must, therefore, only be varying manifestations of this one substance.” (Besant, 2018, p.88)

The underlying notion is to free oneself from becoming a gendered being. Annie Besant asserts that there is no evidence to prove the existence of God or spirit. She spread the gospel of free thoughts:

“. . . we will spread the Gospel of Freethought among men, until the sad minor melodies of Christianity have sobbed out their last mournful notes on the dying evening breeze, and on the fresh morning winds shall ring out the chorus of hope and joyfulness, from the glad lips of men whom the Truth has at last set free.” (Besant, 2018, p. 102)

According to her, men and women are too made up of different sets of matter only and gender in itself does not have any essence or intrinsic reality. There is nothing like predefined roles and responsibilities. The effect of science, which continuously started overwhelming her, made her believe only in biologists and chemists to seek the explanation of all problems of life and existence. When, in the chapter “Atheism as I Knew and Taught it” focused for research, she defines life which according to her is just the result of the arrangement of matter, it is evidently drawn that she could talk about women’s liberation and gender equality so openly because she considered that biologically and chemically male and female bodies are just the arrangement of different sets of matter.  She appears to be very close to Simone de Beauvoir’s “One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman” when she says:

“There is no sign here of an intelligent spirit controlling a mechanism; there is every sign of a learning and developing intelligence, developing paripassu with the organism of which it is a function.” (Besant, 2018, p. 93)

According to Besant, a human being is just the result of what his parents were and what his circumstances were. There is nothing inborn. He can change the circumstances, make them good or bad, lead a happy and healthy life or a criminal’s life as per his own will. This again reflects Butler’s idea of performativity according to which gender is mainly the performative repetition. The concept of gender is not natural or innate. Besant while advocating that everything is the process of learning is entering into the realm of rejecting the traditional and religious definitions of gender roles. She considers that the crimes against women are sometimes perpetuated by religion:

“Another bestial tendency is the lust of the male for the female apart from love, duty, and loyalty; this again has been encouraged by religion, as witness the polygamy and concubinage of the Hebrews—as in Abraham, David, and Solomon, not to mention the precepts of the Mosaic laws—the bands of male and female prostitutes in connection with Pagan temples, and the curious outbursts of sexual passion in connection with religious revivals and missions.” (Besant, 2018, p. 103)

Many bestial tendencies among human beings are the result of blindly following the religious teachings. She is speaking contrary to the general beliefs of the people that during adversities even the atheists turn towards religion, “For troubles and adversities do more bow men’s minds to religion” (Francis Bacon’s Of Atheism).

Her atheism and the rejection of the idea of God gave her the strength to believe that it is science and not religion that can eradicate such evils by tracing them to their source in the brute ancestry. Human beings can evolve without any discrimination only by losing faith in religion and gaining faith in science. Moreover, a theist can yearn for personal perfection but that will be a self-centered desire. As various religions have divided the people on the basis of class, colour, and gender, a theist will never be able to think scientifically. On the contrary, an atheist desires personal perfection not for his selfish motives but rather because science has taught him the unity of the race and gender too.

  1. Conclusion:

Annie Besant, thus, grasping the complexities of the situation of women tried the idea of atheism as a religion in itself. It is her continuous rejection of the religion — as is evident in the chapter taken up for study — gave her the strength to work for the poor and oppressed women of the country. Making humanity, not religiosity as her surging passion, she could easily attack the prevailing system of injustice and hardships. She organized trade unions, campaigned for birth control, helped in rising the age of marriage, abolishing Pardah system, and educating girls and women. She left her imprints on the sands of time. Her journey from a devout Christian to a free thinker gave her the necessary strength to fight against the patriarchal religious discourses constructing the performative identities and making them appear innate and natural.

Declaration of Conflict of Interests

The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest.

Funding

No funding has been received for the publication of this article. It is published free of any charge.

References:

Bacon, Francis. (1908). Of Atheism. The Essays of Francis Bacon. Ed. Mary Augusta Scott. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. 71-75

Beauvoir, Simone de. (2010). The Second Sex. New York: Vintage.

Besant, Annie. (2018).  Atheism As I Knew and Taught It. An Autobiography. London: Global Grey. 88-110. 

Besant, Annie.  (1877). The Gospel of Atheism. London: Freethought.

Besant, Annie.  (1885). Political Status of Women, 1874, 2nd edition. London: C. Watts.

Besant, Annie. (2011). My Path to Atheism. 3rd edition. Retrieved from https://www.gutenberg.org/files/37234/37234-h/37234-h.htm

Butler, Judith. (2001). Subjects of Sex/ Gender/ Desire. The Cultural Studies. Ed. Simon During. London: Routledge.  340-354

Conrad, Nickolas G. (May 2009). Marginalization of Atheism in Victorian Britain: The Trials of Annie Besant and Charles Bradlaugh. Washington State University, Department of History. Retrieved from https://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.427.6882&rep=rep1&type=pdf

Foucault, Michel. (1970). The Order of Discourse. Untying the Text: A Post-Structuralist Reader, Ed. Robert Young, Boston: Routledge, pp 52-53

Gupta, Tanu. (2021). Pure/Fallen: Understanding the Discursive Construction of Identity in Binodini Dasi’s My Story and My Life as an Actress. Literary Voice. 13(1). 219-214.

Janssen, Flore. (27 November 2017). Talking about Birth Control in 1877: Gender, Class, and Ideology in the Knowlton Trial. Open Cultural Studies, 1(1). 281-290

Jeffrey, Bob and Geoff Troman.  (2011). The Construction of Performative Identities. European Educational Research Journal, 10(4). 484-501

Kamrath, Mark L. (September 2018). Early America, American Theosophy, Modernity—and India. Rupkatha Journal on Interdisciplinary Studies in Humanities, 7(2). 9-20. Retrieved from http://rupkatha.com/V7/n2/02_American_Theosophy_India.pdf

King, Ursula. Hinduism and Women: Uses and Abuses of Religious Freedom. Facilitating Freedom of Religion or Belief: A Deskbook. 523-543. Retrieved from https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-5616-7_22

Lewis, Jone Johnson. Annie Besant, Heretic: The Story of Annie Besant: Minister’s Wife to Atheist to Theosophist. Retrieved from https://www.thoughtco.com/annie-besant-heretic-3529122

Miller, Elizabeth Carolyn. (Summer 2009). The Radical Autobiographies of Annie Besant and Helen and Olivia Rossetti.  Feminist Studies, 35(2).  243-273. Retrieved from https://www.jstor.org/stable/40607966

Miquel-Baldellou, Marta. (noviembre 2009). Annie Besant’s Sexual Politics of Marriage in Victorian England. Clepsydra, 8. 91-110

Moosavi, Zohreh. (2016). The Importance of Chastity and Modesty in Leader Women in the New Testament and Quran. Retrieved from SSRN: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2882423

Nancy, Anderson Fix. (1994) Bridging Cross-Cultural Feminisms: Annie Besant and Women’s Rights in England and India, 1874-1933. Women’s History Review, 3(4). New York: Routledge. 563-580. Retrieved from https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/09612029400200070

Overall, C. (2007). Feminism and Atheism. The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Ed. M. Martin. New York: Cambridge University Press. 233-249

Pillai, Manu S. (Oct. 6, 2017.). Annie Besant: An inconvenient woman. Retrieved from https://www.livemint.com/Leisure/dgXf29xjFPwLz9gYAJotDN/Annie-Besant-An-inconvenient-woman.html

Prabhakaran, A. (June-2019). Role of Annie Besant in Women’s Indian Association (WIA) – A Study. Research Review International Journal of Multidisciplinary, 4(6). Retrieved from https://www.researchgate.net/publication/333867281_Role_of_Annie_Besant_in_Women’s_Indian_Association_WIA_-A_Study

Singh, C.L. (2018). Making “ideal” Indian women: Annie Besant’s engagement with the issue of female education in early twentieth-century India. International Journal of the History of Education, 54(5). 606-625

Stinson, Rebecca D., Kathleen M. Goodman, and Saba R. Ali. (2013). Do Atheism and Feminism Go Hand-in-Hand? A Qualitative Investigation of Atheist Men’s Perspectives about Gender Equality. Secularism and Nonreligion. Retrieved from https://www.researchgate.net/publication/237074877_Do_Atheism_and_Feminism_Go_Hand-in-Hand_A_Qualitative_Investigation_of_Atheist_Men’s_Perspectives_about_Gender_ Equality

Ylivuori, Soile. (March 2016). Rethinking Female Chastity and Gentlewoman’s Honour in Eighteenth Century England. The Historical Journal.59(1). 71-97

Dr. Tanu Gupta is Professor of English in University Institute of Liberal Arts and Humanities at Chandigarh University. She received Ph.D. from Punjabi University, Patiala. Her research interests include Gender, Psychoanalytic and Postcolonial studies. She is the author of more than 80 research articles and 7 books.

Reason: Pedagogy and Complementarity in Marguerite Porete’s The Mirror of Simple Souls

/
528 views

Javiera Steck1 & Josefa Vecchiola2

1Universidad de Chile. ORCID: 0000-0002-1169-7304. Email: javiera.steck@ug.uchile.cl

2Universidad de Chile. ORCID: 0000-0002-3438-1062. Email: josefa.vecchiola@ug.uchile.cl

Rupkatha Journal, Vol. 14, Issue 2, April-June, 2022, Pages  https://doi.org/10.21659/rupkatha.v14n2.13

First published: June 20, 2022 | Area: Scientific Philosophy | License: CC BY-NC 4.0

(This article is published under Volume 14, Number 2, 2022)
Full-Text HTML Full-Text PDF Cite
PlumX Metrics

Abstract

The purpose of this article is to explore the role of reason in The Mirror of Simple Souls by Medieval French Beguine Marguerite Porete (c. 1250-1310). Our first strategy will be revising the function of Reason as a character throughout the text’s dialogues, in which Reason, Love, and Soul participate as main characters. Secondly, we intend to compare Reason and Love, as well as to understand whether these different forms of intellect are complementary or opposite to each other in some way, given the text’s inscription in a premodern Medieval philosophy. Finally, we would like to understand reason within the frame of the possible pedagogical uses that Marguerite conferred to it in her text.  

Keywords: Marguerite Porete, Love, Reason, Medieval Female Mysticism, Intellectus rationis, Intellectus amoris, Pedagogy.

In the following study, we intend to explore, in the first place, why French Beguine and mystic Marguerite Porete (13th-14th c.) inserted Reason as one of the main characters from her renowned book The Mirror of Simple Souls, a dialogical treatise. Mystic experience (that is, the experience of union with God) is commonly presented in the medieval female mystic tradition as that which transcends the comprehensible or the perceivable through reason. That is why the insertion and centrality of Reason as an allegoric character and mediator require a deeper examination since this prominence is not self-explanatory as mystic experience does not conceive Reason as the only means to its complete fulfilment. Exploring the possibilities of this question about Reason’s protagonism opens two paths. The first points toward the –in our opinion, quite fruitful– comparison between the allegoric characters of Love and Reason so as to understand if their relationship is one of opposition or complementarity, by associating those perspectives with the different philosophical traditions coexisting in the Middle Ages[1]. On the other hand, the second path leads us to propose the possible pedagogical usefulness of incorporating the allegoric character of Reason in The Mirror of Simple Souls.

To elaborate on all of the above we must, firstly, briefly identify the character of Reason. This appears in the first part of The Mirror (chapters 1 to 122), where a group of allegoric characters are introduced: Love, Reason, and Annihilated Soul being the main characters and the ones who take part in a collaborative dialogue. These characters give an account of Love’s crucial role in Marguerite’s text: to show lost souls the way towards the Country of Liberty[2]. It is by Love’s hand that we can see Reason for the first time as part of a mystic experience. Love states:

“Hijos de la Santa Iglesia -dice Amor-, por vosotros he hecho este libro, a fin de que oigáis, para valeros mejor, la perfección de la vida y el estado de paz a los que puede llegar en virtud de la caridad perfecta de la criatura a la que le es concedido este don de toda la Trinidad. Don del que oiréis dirimir en este libro a través de las respuestas de Entendimiento de Amor a las preguntas de Razón” (Porete, 2005, p. 35).

“Children of the Holy Church –says Love-, for you I have made this book, so you can hear, so you can better make use of life’s perfection and the state of peace to which it can get to, by virtue of the creature’s perfect charity upon which the gift of the whole Trinity is bestowed. A gift about which you will hear its settling in this book through the answers of the Understanding of Love to the questions of Reason” (Porete, 2015, p. 34-35)[3].

Questioning through dialogue is the communicative entrance with which the character of Reason is present and inserted in The Mirror. From Love’s wisdom and Reason’s rational questions (which identify the souls under Reason’s rule and, hence, attached to Virtues), a window is opened to elucidate the paths that can lead the soul to its liberty. Thus, ordinary people will be able to comprehend the insufficiency of the very same reasoning they make use of. An example of such dialogue is the following:

“Razón: Pero, dama Amor —dice Razón—, querríamos, si os place, entender bien y más abiertamente ese don?que el Espíritu Santo da a tales Almas (…).?Amor: ¡Ay, Razón! —dice Amor—, siempre seréis tuertos vos y los que se alimentan de vuestra doctrina. Pues ciertamente está medio ciego el que tiene las cosas delante de los ojos y no las reconoce. Y es lo que os pasa a vos” (Porete, 2005, p. 82).? 

“Reason: But, lady Love –says Reason–, we would want, if you please, to understand better and more openly that gift which the Holy Spirit gives to such Souls (…). Love: ¡Ah, Reason! –says Love–, you will always be one-eyed, you and the ones that feed from your doctrine. For, certainly, he who has things before his eyes yet still doesn’t recognise them is half blind. And that’s what happens to you” (Porete, 2005, p. 82).

However, considering all of the above, it’s crucial to ponder the following: why is there a predominant presence of Reason if we, as readers, are facing the tale and teachings of a mystic experience which is unintelligible under rational principles? To answer this question, we have to notice that, first, the road to perfection proposed by Porete entails seven states moving upwards from “el abandono del pecado hasta la gloria” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.327) (“the renunciation of sin to glory”), of which the first four states remain under the rule of Reason, while the other three are governed by Love. Secondly, we must note that said path implies three instances of death (those of sin, of nature, and of spirit), and two downfalls: the fall of Virtues into Love and the fall of Love into Nothing “que lleva al alma al más profundo anonadamiento de sí, capaz de renunciar al propio Amor por amor” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.327) (“which leads the soul to the deepest annihilation of itself, capable of giving up Love for love”), a moment that depicts the descending path. In regard to this, it’s fundamental to highlight that it is precisely in the change from Reason’s domain to Love’s where Marguerite Porete’s main concern is to be found, since, as Garí points out, she:

“le interesa sobre todo enseñar cómo se alcanza ese estado, es decir, mostrar el paso entre ambos regímenes, el de la Razón y el del Amor, que es a la vez el de la muerte al espíritu y el que asciende del cuarto al quinto nivel de perfección” (Porete, 2005, p. 23).

“is, above all, interested in teaching how to reach that state, that is to say, showing the passage between both regimes, Reason’s and Love’s, which is at the same time the one of death to the spirit and the one that ascends from the fourth to the fifth level of perfection” (Porete, 2005, p. 23).

Also, it is worth mentioning that to understand the importance of Reason through the path the lost ones start, and the passing from one regime to the other, it’s necessary to acknowledge the fact that this road entails highlighting begging as the very first step lost souls take before arriving in the state of liberty, and that these begging as the action takes place, precisely, under Reason’s rule. In Soul’s case, present throughout Porete’s text, begging occurs first when the pleading creature, as they try to find God, makes use of rational tools such as thinking and writing.

“Y cuando vio que no encontraba nada, se puso a pensar; y su pensamiento le dijo que fuera a buscar lo que reclamaba en el fondo nodal del entendimiento de la pureza de su supremo pensar, y allí fue a buscarlo esta mendicante criatura, y pensó que escribiría sobre Dios de la manera como quería encontrarlo en sus criaturas. Y así escribió esta mendicante lo que estáis oyendo” (Porete, 2015, p.136) (la cursiva es nuestra).

“And when she saw that she didn’t find anything, she began to think; and her thought told her to go look for what she was claiming in the nodal fund of her supreme thinking’s understanding of purity, and there she went looking for it, this begging creature, and thought that she would write about God in the way she wanted to find him in her creatures. And so, this beggar wrote what you are hearing” (Porete, 2005, p.136) (italics are ours). 

And then, she resorts to the questions:

“pues preguntando puede llegarse lejos, y preguntando puede encontrarse el propio camino, o reencontrarse si se ha salido de él” (Porete, 2015, p.170) (la cursiva es nuestra).

“since by asking you can go far, and by asking you can find your own way, or find yourself again if you have left it” (Porete, 2005, p. 170) (italics are ours).

Thinking, writing, and questioning are tools, then, that involve a rational logic that, even though they lead the Soul to beg for it is still too soon to have an encounter with God, they set the start of the road for these souls to arrive at the so awaited dejection which, let’s not forget, occurs in those states of most elevated understanding governed by Love. However, the one who recognises in this treatise the importance of such an action (begging) as a rational and erratic, though necessary, the process is indeed the allegoric character of Soul, who is, also, convinced of this need. All of what we have exposed so far can be seen in Soul’s confession to Trinity when she mentions the importance of creatures begging:

“El Alma:  Cierto, pues es necesario hacerlo antes de llegar en todo al estado de libertad, estoy segura. Y con todo —dice esta Alma que escribió este libro—era tan necia en la época en que lo escribí, o más bien que Amor lo hizo por mí a petición mía, que ponía precio a cosas que no se podían hacer, pensar ni decir, como haría aquel que quisiera encerrar el mar en su ojo, llevar el mundo sobre la punta de un junco, e iluminar el sol con un farol o una antorcha. Era más necia que quien quisiera hacer estas tres cosas. Cuando puse precio a lo que no podía decirse/ y me hallé presa en escribir estas palabras./ Pero así emprendí mi camino/ para acudir en mi propio socorro,/ y alcanzar al fin la cúspide del estado del que hablamos/que es el de la perfección” (Porete, 2015, p. 137- 138) (la cursiva es nuestra).

“Soul: True, for it’s necessary to do it before getting completely to the state of liberty, I’m sure. And yet –says this Soul that wrote this book– I was so foolish at the time that I wrote it, or rather that Love wrote it for me at my request, that I put a price on things that cannot be done, thought nor said, as would do the one who wanted to lock the sea within his eye, carry the world on the tip of a reed, and illuminate the sun with a lantern or a torch. I was more foolish than someone who’d want to do those three things. When I put price to what cannot be said | and I found myself prisoner of writing these words. | But that’s how I started my way | to come to my own rescue, | and to reach finally the cusp of the state which we talk about | that is of perfection” (Porete, 2005, p. 137-138) (italics are ours).

The role of Reason through Soul’s journey to the Country of Liberty is also illuminated in her appearance as the “gatekeeper” of said path, a metaphor that identifies her as an initiator of the way to God. In Porete’s words:

“Razón: ¡Ah, por Dios, dama Amor! -dice Razón-, dinos qué será de Vergüenza, la más bella de las hijas de Humildad; y también de Temor, que tantos bienes ha hecho al Alma y tantos bellos servicios; y qué será de mí misma, que no he dormido mientras me han necesitado. ¡Ay de mí! -dice Razón-. ¿Nos echará de su casa ahora que ha alcanzado señoría?

Amor: ¡No, no! -dice Amor-. Al contrario, vosotras tres permaneceréis en su mesnada y seréis las tres guardianas de su puerta, de forma que nadie que vaya contra Amor pueda penetrar en su casa sin que os despertéis; pero no os comportéis de ninguna otra manera más que como porteras, pues si no os veríais confundidas; y no seréis escuchadas en ningún caso más que como tales” (Porete, 2015, p. 103) (la cursiva es nuestra).

“Reason: Ah, by God, lady Love! –says Reason–, tell us what will become of Shame, the most beautiful of Humility’s daughters; and also of Fear, that so many goods have done to Soul and so many beautiful services; and what will be of myself, that I haven’t slept while I’ve been needed. Woe is me! –says Reason–. Will you throw us out of her house now that you’ve reached ladyship?

Love: No, no! –says Love–. On the contrary, you three will remain in her legion and will be the three guardians of her door, so that no one who’s against Love can penetrate into her house without waking you up; but do not behave in any other way than as doorkeepers, since if you do, you would see yourselves confused; and you won’t be listened to in any case more than as such” (Porete, 2005, p. 144).

In this way, we observe (as Laura Durán does in her article about The Mirror, whom we paraphrase in what follows) that when Reason asks Love what will become of her and her servants (Virtues), Love answers that they will remain as “porteras de la casa del Alma” (Durán, 2021, p.20) (“doorkeepers of Soul’s house”), therefore, it is Reason who first discerns what kind of behaviour leads or not to the path of God.

To forgive, to write, to think, to ask oneself: all of them are actions with an initiatory sense, but, furthermore, these are actions that Soul carries out the moment she embarks on an inner quest. As Garí states in her article:

“Margarita busca primero en el mundo [exterior] un espejo donde reconocerse y no encuentra nada; al interiorizar entonces su búsqueda hace de su entendimiento un espejo que refleja lo divino sobre el mundo” (Garí, 1995, p.60).

“Marguerite seeks in the [exterior] world a mirror where to recognise herself and she doesn’t find anything; when interiorising, then, her search she makes of her understanding a mirror that reflects the divine upon the world” (Garí, 1995, p. 60).

Like Garí, we observe that the beginning of the mystical path is the interiorization of the quest, and the first stage of such process is marked by reflection, mediation, question, thinking that is begging, also, writing, which is especially capable of revealing or, at least, investigating Porete’s Soul’s inner “I”. Reason has, hence, a fundamental and initial place in the experience. The centrality of Reason’s role is due to both her initial and mediating importance and to Soul’s need to abandon her in order to reach the encounter with God.  In mystic experience, Reason is the border that must be trespassed.

Complementarity or Opposition? Love and Reason in Medieval Mysticism.

The starting point for the assessment of a likely opposition or complement of the characters of Love and Reason is to observe the extent to which each of them possesses a coupled form of understanding, inasmuch as Marguerite Porete sees both of them as paths of knowledge. The result is clear: Reason’s understanding tends to judgement, is insufficient, and cannot comprehend what is essential within mystic experience, as it is, according to Porete, a “too low” understanding for it to “highly comprehend”, in contrast to divine Love’s understanding, who “comprende bien y sin obstáculos” (Porete, 2015, p.48) (“comprehends well and with no obstacles”).

The reason is not, then, a likely vehicle for reaching the highest levels of liberty of the soul, as neither are institutions and instances that unfold under their law. In other words, Virtues, the Sacred Scriptures, and the Holy Church (“the little one”, as Porete calls it). In this way, Love and Reason are, to some extent, contrary, because Reason’s understanding, due to its own constitution (rational, argumentative, inquisitive), cannot comprehend Love’s understanding nor the possibilities for liberation that it offers. Love’s understanding, inextricably associated with divinity, is in itself an intuitive knowledge that derives from the unitive experience or God Himself; a knowledge that presents itself as clarification, without human rationality’s mediation. To Durán, as in Marguerite Porete’s case as in Mechthild of Magdeburg’s:

“es por amor que el alma se une a Dios y, en tanto tal, el amor tiene un lugar por sobre el pensamiento o conocimiento… [que es] posibilitado sólo por el Amor”(Durán, 2021, p.22),

“it’s because of love that the soul is united with God and, as such, love has a place above thinking or knowledge… [which is] enabled only by Love” (Durán, 2021, p. 22)

As to Garí, Love’s understanding “refleja la experiencia del alma como experiencia de un saber que se es” (Garí, 1995, p-60) (“reflects the experience of the soul as an experience of knowing that you are”), which is also “saber-otro que se sitúa más allá de la ley, de la razón mediadora” (Garí, 1995, p.58)[4] (“other knowledge situated beyond the law, beyond mediating reason”).

In The Mirror, though, we see that this difference of capabilities between both intellects is acknowledged by Reason, which is clearly seen when she states:

“esto no lo puede entender nadie a no ser que lo aprenda de vos [Amor] a través de vuestras enseñanzas, pero no a través de mi entendimiento” (Porete, 2015, p. 50).

“nobody can understand this unless they learn this from you through your teachings, but not by means of my understanding” (Porete, 2015, p.50).

Although, based on Love and Reason’s contrary abilities, we could state that they are in an opposition relationship –an opposition that is also completely hierarchical, in which Love is deliberately superior and annuls the importance of Reason–, the reality in The Mirror is different. If we read carefully, we can observe that, indeed, the rule of reason is an absolutely necessary step in the mystical path toward the union with God. It is not replaceable nor expendable, since, as we already saw, it possesses an initiatory role: reason is the first step inwards, marked by thought, doubt, the soul’s plead, and the exercise of questioning. It happens that institutions and instances existing under the law of Reason are Christianity’s first school, hence strictly necessary for starting the journey to liberty. It is through them that ordinary people get to know the Christian doctrine, as they also apprehend with these institutions the first models of Christian piety, charity (Mary, mother of God, but also Mary Magdalene and John the Baptist), and the Holy Trinity, examples that allow the adoption of Christianity’s main maxims and God’s wishes in one’s life. The reason, further, is necessary for mystic experience due to another factor. Reasoning is the dialectic instance which, through thought and inner questioning over God, allows the Soul to understand the need for negation, overcoming, and transcendence of Reason herself: only the excess of Reason allows Reason’s liberation – an absolutely necessary step, as we saw, for the road from the liberation of the soul to the encounter with God –, which can be seen in Love’s statement below:

“Pero ahora, esta Alma ha ganado y aprendido tanto con las Virtudes que está por encima de ellas” (Porete, 2015, p. 60)

“But now, this Soul has won and learnt so much with Virtues that it is above them.” (Porete, 2015, p. 60)

Here we observe that the soul that looks for its own liberation learns, in the first place, from Virtues, and only after that learning, it comes to be “above” them, a moment that coincides with the passing from Reason’s government to Love’s.

Reason and Love, then, are not actually related in opposition. Instead, they collaborate with each other, as it can be seen when Love expresses her willingness to dialogue with Reason and the latter, in turn, points out that she will not “tener mayor gozo ni mayor honor que el de ser sierva de tal señora” (Porete, 2015, p. 78) (“have grater joy nor honour than that of being the servant of such lady”). So that Reason finds herself voluntarily in the service of Love.

In regard to the initiatory role of Reason’s understanding, the following fragment is particularly illustrative:

“Razón: ¿Cuándo estuvieron sujetas las almas? Amor: Cuando permanecieron en el amor y la obediencia a vos, dama Razón, y también a las otras Virtudes;?y tanto permanecieron que se hicieron libres” (Porete, 2015, p. 40) (la cursiva es nuestra).

“Reason: When were the souls subject? Love: When they remained in love and obedience to you, Lady Reason, and to the other Virtues; and too long they endured that they made themselves free”.  (Porete, 2015, p. 40) (italics are ours).

Here, certainly, continuity is shown between the passage from Reason’s understanding to Love’s as complementary and integrated parts of the same process. In this respect, we must remark that complementarity between Love and Reason is not a fortuitous event[5]. Indeed, the notion of complementarity is illuminated if we point out an historical-philosophical approach to The Mirror. During the High Middle Ages (9th-10th c.) there were two philosophical theories developed around sexual difference: the theory of complementarity of the sexes and the theory of Aristotelian polarity[6]. Furthermore, a part of European Feudal thought envisioned that “el amor es un intelecto, uno de los dos intelectos con los que nace cada criatura humana” (Rivera, 2005, p.103) (“love was an intellect, one of the two intellects each human creature is born with”) where both intellects are intellectus rationis and intellectus amoris, that is to say, the intelligence of reason and the intelligence of love, where the latter is typically associated with feminine understanding. It is in this tradition of thought were Porete is located along with other mystic women. Regarding the existing gender-intellect correspondence during the High Middle Ages, Cirlot and Garí remark:

“la teología era el dominio de los hombres, el de la alta cultura. La visión dicotómica, tan propia de la cultura medieval, siempre repartidora de funciones, hizo recaer la experiencia en las mujeres. En una ordenación del mundo a partir de los géneros, a lo masculino correspondían la cultura clerigal, la escritura, el latín, el conocimiento teologal, mientras que a lo femenino correspondían lo laico, la oralidad, las lenguas vulgares, la experiencia” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.38),

“theology was men’s domain, that of high culture. The dichotomous vision, so typical of Medieval culture, always distributing functions, made experience fall on women. In a world order based on gender, to the masculine corresponded clerical culture, writing, theological knowledge, while to the feminine corresponded the secular, orality, vulgar languages, experience” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.38),

Thus, we identify a gender-based distinction of understandings. Regarding, in addition, that during this period, along with the proliferation of a new feminine spirituality[7], that proposes the vindication of women’s intellect (the understanding of Love), feminine mysticism thus takes distance from “la enseñanza teológica y teórica y a la mediación con las instituciones ofrecidas en esa relación por la figura masculina del sacerdote” (Cirlot &Garí, 2021, p.26) (“the theological and theoretical teaching and the mediation of institutions offered in such relationship by the male figure of the priest”), fundamentally identified with the law and rationality (intellect) associated with men, while “conocimiento experiencial femenino (…) exige para sí el reconocimiento de su relación inmediata con lo Divino” (Cirlot & Garí, 1999, p.26) (“feminine experiential knowledge (…) demands for itself the acknowledgement of its direct relationship to the Divine”).

Throughout this period, then, the theory of polarity of the sexes implied the defense of the legitimacy of one of the intellects, i.e., the intellectus rationis, which was identified as masculine, establishing a hierarchy that underrated the intellectus amoris, according to women’s inferiority, at the same time that, in such context of epistemic tension, medieval mystic women were the ones who, with their writings, depicted intellectus amoris as an absolutely key element in the configuration of their experience[8], defending its relevance and value (as we can see, this happens with the role of Love in The Mirror)[9]. Therefore, this exercise constitutes the legitimation of an understanding typically considered feminine, and with that, the legitimation of women’s authority as knowledge-producer subjects, usually through intellectus amoris –or knowledge through intuition– since:

“En la mística femenina, el amor a Dios no es una idea, sino una experiencia terrible en la que el alma arrastra al cuerpo a participar en ella” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.42),

“In feminine Mysticism, love for God is not an idea, but a terrible experience in which the soul drags the body to take part in it” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.42),

experience that altogether takes place in the woman’s body. Why? Because, according to the thinking of the time, “Dios se había querido manifestar a lo más inferior, a lo más frágil, que dentro de los valores medievales profundamente misóginos eran las mujeres” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.38) (“God had wanted to show Himself to the most inferior, the most fragile, to that which, in the deeply misogynistic medieval values, were women”), so much so that even when men were those who experimented the unitive experience – such as Master Eckhart, his disciple Henry Suso, as well as Saint John of the Cross, all of them after the bloom of twelfth-and-thirteenth-century Medieval Feminine Mysticism– “la feminización constituía la necesaria humillación para la unión con Dios”” (Cirlot & Garí, 2021, p.39) (“feminisation constituted the necessary humiliation for the union with God).

In this sense, our reading of The Mirror of Simple Souls is supportive of other scholar’s perspectives, for example, Blanca Garí and Laura Durán who are quoted here, in which we, as they either do, see in Medieval Mystic writings as a vindication of love’s intellect –a confirmation that love is a fundamentally feminine legitimate and necessary path of knowledge– and with that the authority of women, in contrast to the predominance that learned theology and scholastics had enjoyed until when talking about God.

Nonetheless, our goal is to also emphasise, besides Love’s understanding’s vindication –an absolutely key element in The Mirror-, the readiness for conciliation with Reason’s intellect. In other words, Marguerite Porete does not show total rejection of what then was seen as a masculine ability, but she offers a possibility for integrating both understandings, an integration whose ultimate goal is to arrive at the union with the Divine. To be clear: this necessary character of Reason for the path to God is not an interpretative novelty of our own. This has been pointed out by Blanca Garí, for instance, who affirms that the text The Mirror of Simple Souls would not make sense without Reason’s participation, even in spite of the fact the book itself represents her as “desentendimiento” (Garí, 1995, p.61) (“misunderstanding”), as well as Garí states that

 “Razón … es la gran mediadora de la libertad, [ya que] a través de ella llegan los rayos de Entendimiento [al Alma] que ella misma no entiende” (Garí, 1995, p.64);

“Reason… is the greatest mediator of liberty, [since] through her the rays of understanding reach [the Soul] that she herself does not comprehend” (Garí, 1995, p.64);

and, in similar way, it appears mentioned in Durán’s work:

“La palabra de Amor no se debe contradecir (…) Razón es la oponente de Amor, facultad que debe morir para que el Alma alcance su transformación. Con todo, Razón es esencial en la conversión” (Durán, 2021, p.15) (la cursiva es nuestra).

“Love’s word must not be challenged (…) Reason is the opponent of Love, the faculty that must die for the Soul to reach its transformation. With all, Reason is essential in the conversion” (Durán, 2021, p.15) (Italics are ours).

What we want to do, regarding the acknowledgement of the need for Reason as our basis, is to show an emphasise this wish about integrating understanding, and rethink this in relation to the terms with which sex was thought about during this part of the Middle Ages, so that the defence of both intellects’ complementarity implies a defence of sexual complementarity, of human capabilities as a whole. Thereby, we observe that the treatment of Reason as a necessary element in the mystical pathway, from an author, who at the same time assigns Love’s understanding one of the highest qualities, obeys an integration impetus of constructing a thinking and undivided existence, but integral and complex in its multiplicity.

In this manner, we assert that Medieval mystic Marguerite Porete’s genius (we stick, for now, to what we have seen so far in The Mirror of Simple Souls) is not limited to simply inverting the hierarchical binomial established around sex (thence, around intellect) by the Aristotelian polarity theory, binomial where, formerly, Reason and the masculine voice had the authority to talk about God. However, after having fiercely defended intellectus amoris’ legitimacy in her mystic experience, she also advocates for the legitimacy and need of intellectus rationis (allegorically embodied by Reason in The Mirror) as the main backbone of our spiritual experience. It seems to us that, perfectly in tune with the philosophy of complementarity of the sexes, The Mirror transfers this complementarity to its correlate in the two possible understandings for the human being. This implies that Reason and Love complement each other and, once they are integrated into the other, constitute a totality. Reason in The Mirror is no less for taking an initiatory role. Marguerite Porete does not propose a progressive hierarchy, but a conjunction of opposites in an order, where its two constituents are necessary conditions for the inner path ahead.

Reason: One of the Pedagogical Strategies to Teach the Road to Perfection.

Resuming our questioning about Reason’s protagonism, let us remember that the second path that is opened is due to the proposal concerning the possible pedagogic use of incorporating this allegorical character in The Mirror of Simple Souls. For this, let’s stop with the fact that Marguerite Porete, since she started writing about her vital experience about searching for God, does not only produce a mere narrative about her, but she also presents us:

“(…)?un tratado didáctico, mistagógico, que pretende comunicar a otros y otras esa experiencia, y que pretende enseñar desde ella” (Cirlot & Garí, 1999, p.237).

“(…) a mystagogical, didactic treatise, that intends to communicate to others such experience, and that wants to teach from it” (Cirlot & Garí, 1999, p.237).

Writing, then, could be for Marguerite Porete the pathway that leads her towards perfection, and the dialogue she inserts in her text, one of the pedagogical methods for passing through the seven stages and three deaths. Further, that interaction is composed by the same authorities, that is to say, Love and Annihilated Soul, in a manner that both characters confer legitimacy to their own discourse thanks to their contact to and direct knowledge of God.

From said argumentative, didactic dialogue contained within the first part of The Mirror, where Marguerite Porete inserts the character of Reason, and that, shows her true pedagogical intention for the Simple Souls to understand and learn from The Mirror by reading it, we could infer that Porete –first of all– does not completely abandon the argumentative logic in which Reason remains locked. In fact, she gives Reason space to reflect within the dialogue, because she asks about ordinary people. This character speaks from intellectus rationis and no from the logic of the active and the contemplative, logic that for Reason are just “palabras de doble sentido que se hacen difícil de comprender para su entendimiento” (Porete, 2015, p.49) (“double-meaning words that make themselves difficult for their understanding”). It is because of this that we believe Reason (as an allegoric character) is put in the work as the pedagogic way and strategy to catch those souls that are still under Reason’s rule and that, by feeling identified with her presence, manage to start, and be led towards perfection. In Porete’s text that is made evident when Reason, repeatedly asks Love to clarify some doubts for ordinary people. An example of that can be seen in Chapter 13 when Reason says:

“Ahora, Amor -dice Razón-, habéis condescendido a nuestros ruegos aclarando las cosas para los activos y los contemplativos; pero os ruego aún que se lo aclaréis a la gente común, algunos de los cuales podrían por ventura alcanzar este estado. (…) y si se lo explicáis, este libro mostrará a todos la verdadera luz de la verdad (…)” (Porete, 2015, p. 49).

“Now, Love –says Reason– you have condescended to our pleas clarifying things for the active and contemplative; but I still beg you to clarify this to ordinary people, some of them might, by chance, reach this state (…) and if you explained this, this book would show everybody the true light of truth (…)” (Porete, 2015, p. 49).

The road of experience moves upwards within the dialogue. Yet this ascension to God does not advance linearly – the image of a staircase is insufficient –, otherwise, it’s travelled in the form of a spiral, since the soul’s ascent has the particularity of approaching and taking distance from God, as the sway of a descending feather. It is a form of construction present throughout The Mirror that is guided by the “cercanía y distancia como nudo de la relación amorosa, traducida aquí en amor místico” (Porete, 2005, p.18) (“closeness and distance as a knot of the loving relationship, translated here as mystic love”). The far-close behaviour, set up from the courtly novel[10], is present from the beginning, specifically in the prologue to The Mirror, when Porete explains her book’s function and with that commits herself to contrast God and Soul’s relationship with that of the King and the maiden’s. According to Coral Cuadrada, this comparison made by Marguerite implies the assertion that:

“El amor humano está relacionado con el divino, que se puede experimentar la unión con Dios sin mediación alguna. (…) Margarita toma de la expresión y de las imágenes cortesanas francesas, con frecuencias utilizadas en la literatura y en la música, representaciones que le sirven para describir la fusión del amor” (Cuadrada, 2018, p. 309).

“Human love is related to the Divine, it’s possible to experience the union with God without any mediation. (…) Marguerite takes from French courtly expressions and images, frequently used in literature and music, useful representations to describing the fusion of love” (Cuadrada, 2018, p.309).

On the other hand, to philosopher Wanda Tommasi:

“hay dos relatos que circunscriben el recorrido del Alma en su itinerario hacia la unión con Dios: el primero se refiere al significado mismo del libro, el segundo a la actitud del alma que “mendiga” a Dios” (Tommasi, 2002, p. 91).

“There are two narratives that circumscribe Soul’s trip in her itinerary towards the union with God: the first one refers to the very meaning of the text, the second to the attitude of the soul that ‘begs’ to God” (Tommasi, 2020, p.91).

And precisely, the first narrative refers to the history of the maiden and King Alexander that is to be found, as we mentioned earlier, in The Mirror’s prologue. Said the above, it is in this comparison of love’s fusion that Marguerite Porete makes between the Soul and God – as opposed to a mundane and courtly love – where we observe Porete’s second major pedagogical strategy, which, although it is not directly related to Reason (nor its pedagogical use just described), it does reveal the author’s authentic pedagogical intention, so that her primordial goal writing The Mirror is to teach, to show the path, for the ordinary people to have an example, in the clearest manner, of how Soul’s way to God is and to accomplish the so awaited unitive experience. If we consider the main purpose of The Mirror teaching, then, the use of Reason as a pedagogical strategy acquires, under this view, even greater importance.

To summarize what has been just said, there are two pedagogical strategies with which Porete illustrates the mystical pathway: the first one is when Reason is conferred a relevant place within the dialogue, and the second, is that of comparing these fusions of love between the Soul/God and maiden/King through characteristic elements of troubadour poetry. Both are strategies of a different kind, but with the same objective: to make the mystic experience’s understanding, throughout her treatise, a more accessible form of knowledge.

It is also important to point out that Love confers Reason, within the treatise, a space for dialogue, debate, and the logical argumentative questioning, despite being conscious that Reason is not at the level of its own knowledge. In this sense, Love’s humility is a fundamental characteristic, because it is the feature that evinces her true pedagogical intention. The purpose and true invitation of Love, then, is for ordinary people to be guided through the discovery of Reason’s insufficiency of knowledge and to overcome it. Love’s will is to dialogue with Reason manifests, too, that there is no intention to rank both forms of understanding, even when Reason’s insufficiency is always an assertion through the dialogues. This is due to the fact that, as we already mentioned, the first states governed by intellectus rationis are, without doubt, necessary for the path that leads Soul to its annihilation.

The question about pedagogy, as we can see in The Mirror, is a crucial matter and it is indeed present throughout the most part of the treatise. We have seen, also, how Marguerite Porete enquires about the use of different narrative strategies as didactic tools to accomplish her goal in The Mirror: “producir un discurso didáctico que tenga efectos en la vida de sus lectores” (Durán, 2021, p.2) (“to produce a didactic discourse that has an effect in the lives of her readers”). Porete’s work, then, is linked to pedagogy since “se pretende comunicar un saber, posibilitado por la experiencia del amor (…)” (Durán, 2021, p.2) (“it intends to communicate knowledge enabled by the experience of love (…)”). A matter that should be highlighted is that the fact that one of Reason’s main functions is her pedagogic role is by no means trivial, not in a context where women were quite limited when teaching about God. This happens, just as Cirlot and Garí assert – and as we have previously seen – at the time of Beguines, Dominicans, and Medieval Franciscans, when there is an emergence of tension between theological and theoretical teaching strictly related to the masculine figure of the priest (seen as the institution’s mediator), as opposed to the feminine experience’s knowledge that claims the recognition of the immediate relationship with the Divine (Cirlot & Garí, 1999, p.26). These two forms are opposed generating a tension that –as said by the aforementioned authors– grows over time, since the proliferation of the latter knowledge –feminine experience– could promote the disappearance and discredit of institutional mediation, for what women remained deliberately excluded from teaching. Actually, Durán comments in a footnote that:

“Enrique de Gante mostró la disposición para permitir a las mujeres -quienes no accedían a la enseñanza universitaria en teología- ejercer un papel restringido como doctoras de teología ex beneficio, por contraposición al ejercicio ex officio” (Durán, 2021, p. 16).

“Henry of Ghent showed the willingness to allow women – who did not have access to university training in theology – to exercise a restricted role as doctors in theology ex beneficio, in contrast to the ex officio practice”. (Durán, 2021, p.16).

Such tension, which is detrimental to those women who felt the need to teach from their experience, refers to Marguerite Porete’s work, and it is Laura Durán who identifies it when she asserts that the personification of Reason (and the other characters), besides allowing the audience to have a “representación de los medios para encontrar a Dios” (Durán, 2021, p.15) (“representation of the means to find God”), it will allow readers to elude the author’s own voice, “quien de este modo evita disculparse por escribir y enseñar siendo mujer” (Durán, 2021, p.16) (“who in this way avoids apologising for writing and teaching being a woman”). Therefore, we can say that pedagogy is a transversal resource for Medieval mystic women and, as such, a space for resistance where these women –belonging to the “nueva teología [que] se caracterizó por la escritura en lengua vernácula y por el lugar central de la experiencia mística” (Durán, 2021, p.2) (“new theology [that] is characterized for being written in a vernacular language, and for the central place of the mystic experience”) that emerges in the 13th century– conceived it as a place that confronts the historical limitations assigned to them.

Conclusion.

In a conclusion, we consider it fundamental to summarize that Reason’s presence is crucial in The Mirror of Simple Souls for the following reasons. In the first place, because Marguerite Porete’s main concern is to teach Soul’s passage from the Rule of Reason to Love’s government, inasmuch as this is a necessary process for the liberation of the soul – as, at the same time, it is not the only vehicle to reach that goal. The understanding of Reason must be overcome and replaced by the understanding of Love, with whom, notwithstanding, is found in a complementarity relationship regarding the totality of the mystical pathway. Secondly, Reason is the main element because, by being inserted in the dialogue of The Mirror, it is used as a pedagogical tool to guide the soul towards the awaited union with God.

About the Echoes of Love’s understanding and the Idea of Complementarity in the 20th c.

We wish to finish our work by reflecting on the concept of complementarity and its possible resonance in 20th-century female authors’ writings. Certainly, this Theory about the sexes, which also advocated for the legitimacy of another form of knowledge (i.e., intellectus amoris) did not survive Marguerite Porete’s times. Modernity, just as Rivera poses, settled its epistemic foundations on a theory inherited from Aristotelian polarity: Humanism’s unity of the sexes (Rivera, 2005, p.98) which, like its predecessor, only recognizes the value of intellectus rationis, this time associated to a universal and sexually neutral subject.

Intellectus amoris tradition, though, has marginally survived in the echo of Medieval mystic women’s voices: either through the direct reception of their texts (like Master Eckhart’s case in the 13th c., who may have known The Mirror and, more recently, Simone Weil’s case, who read The Mirror when its authorship had not been restored to Marguerite Porete), or through spontaneous feminine philosophical and aesthetical proposals that seek to go back to concepts such as love’s understanding of the search for intellectual and sexual complementarity.

Virginia Woolf, for instance, with her approach to androgyny and the unity of mind in A Room of One’s Own, narrates in one of the final chapters of her essay:

“Porque cuando vi a la pareja subir al taxi, la mente sintió como si luego de dividida, se hubiera adherido de nuevo en una fusión natural. La razón lógica y natural sería que los dos sexos cooperaran. Hay un instinto profundo, aunque irracional, en pro de la teoría de que la unión de hombre y mujer procura la mayor satisfacción, la más cabal felicidad. Pero la vista de dos personas subiendo al taxi y la satisfacción que eso me produjo, hizo que también me preguntara si no habría en el espíritu dos sexos, correspondientes a los dos en el cuerpo, y si no sería preciso unirlos para lograr completa satisfacción y felicidad. Y me puse a delinear de cualquier manera un plano del alma, en el que dos poderes presidían, uno varón y otro hembra; y en el cerebro del hombre el varón predomina, y en el cerebro de la mujer la hembra predomina. El estado normal y placentero es cuando están los dos en armonía, colaborando espiritualmente. Hasta en un hombre, la parte femenina del cerebro debe ejercer influencia; y tampoco la mujer debe rehuir contacto con el hombre que hay en ella (…) una gran inteligencia es andrógina” (Woolf, 2010, p.93) (las cursivas son nuestras).

“For certainly when I saw the couple get into the taxi-cab the mind felt as if, after being divided, it had come together again in a natural fusion. The obvious reason would be that it is natural for the sexes to cooperate. One has a profound, if irrational, instinct in favour of the theory that the union of man and woman makes for the greatest satisfaction, the most complete happiness. But the sight of the two people getting into the taxi and the satisfaction it gave me made me also ask whether there are two sexes in the mind corresponding to the two sexes in the body and whether they also require to be united in order to get complete satisfaction and happiness? And I went on amateurishly to sketch a plan of the soul so that in each of us two powers preside, one male, one female; and in the man’s brain the man predominates over the woman, and in the woman’s brain, the woman predominates over the man. The normal and comfortable state of being is that when the two live in harmony together, spiritually co-operating. If one is a man, still the woman part of the brain must have effect; and a woman also must have intercourse with the man in her (…) a great mind is androgynous.” (Woolf, 2015, p. 71).

We can see here that androgyny is, for Woolf, an idea about the mind, a balanced state between the male and female spirits that coexist in the mind of each person, in which both intellects (and the values and forms of writing that, in the first five chapters of A Room of One’s Own, Woolf tries to distinguish them according to sex) collaborate, without impeding creative activity. This is the mind which has total liberty for representation. Thus, the mind that is able to create integral works, faithful to the original vision of its author, requires both understandings: a great intelligence is androgynous (an example of which is Shakespeare). Woolf makes explicit, for all of us women, her ideal of sexual and intellectual complementarity, while she proposes her aesthetic theories about the mental and material conditions that allow the production of integral works of art (particularly novels).

Another woman who has highlighted the concept of complementarity is María Zambrano, with her proposal about the poetic Reason as methodology for thinking. She asserts in her work Claros del bosque:

“Y la visión lejana del centro apenas visible, y la visión que los claros del bosque ofrecen, parecen prometer, más que una visión nueva, un medio de visibilidad donde la imagen sea real y el pensamiento y el sentir se identifiquen sin que sea a costa de que se pierdan el uno en el otro o de que se anulen” (Zambrano, 2019, p.31) (las cursivas son nuestras)

“And the faraway vision of the centre is barely visible, and the vision that forest clearing offer, seem to promise, more than a new vision, a way of visibility where the image is real and the thought and the feeling identify themselves without losing or cancelling each other out” (Zambrano, 2019, p. 31) (italics are ours). 

Here she shows us the vision that emerges from the contemplation of the clearing is the union between feeling and thinking as one: for us, the complementarity of Love and Reason’s understandings. Letting aside the evident similarities between the language used by Zambrano in her work and that used by the Medieval female mystic (a language that puts special emphasis on love, the revelation through poetic beauty, the annihilation, and the ineffable experiences, to say the least). Blanca Garí also explores the relationships between The Mirror of Simple Souls and the text Philosophy and Poetry, another book by Zambrano, in her text Le plus de l’amé regarding these themes. For Garí, this last book by Zambrano “[tiene] el anhelo de reconciliación de ambas, filosofía y poesía, en la razón poética” (Garí, 2010, p.62) (“[has] the longing for the reconciliation of both philosophy and poetry in poetic reason”), as it also shows a rediscovery and reconquest of “la inteligencia de amor y [d]el arte de conocer desde la razo?n mi?stica y la razo?n poe?tica”  (Garí, 2010, p.57) (“the intelligence of love and the art to learn from mystic reason and poetic reason”). We, for our part, note that the proposal of the complementarity of understandings (love and reason) in Zambrano’s work is especially evident, even though the vindication of sexual complementarity is not as explicit as in Woolf’s essay.

To conclude this Little circuit of intertexts between The Mirror and the writings of contemporary authors, we also intuit, as so does Simone Weil, 20th-century philosopher, that this loss of understanding through love –which characterized the transition to Modernity– has been a loss that largely explains this spiritual crisis, but also the social and material ones, in which the West has been constantly submerged. Weil argues, in her writing L’agonie d’une civilisation vue à travers un poème épique, that the effects produced by the Albigensian crusades in Languedoc:

“Europa jamás ha vuelto a encontrar el mismo grado de libertad espiritual que se perdiera como resultado de esa guerra” (Weil, 1960, p. 3).

“Europe has never found the same degree of spiritual liberty that was lost as a result of that war” (Weil, 1960, p. 3).      

In this text, the author does not explicitly mention the notion of intellectual nor sexual complementarity. However, she talks about the alliance between the troubadour culture and the Cathar lifestyle that took place in Languedoc, an alliance that advanced in peace and with a sense of loyalty that, to our view, refers to the importance of love and its corresponding understanding. We agree on this with María Milagros Rivera, who states that Simone Weil “defines Cathar religion and troubadour culture as a civilization: a Mediterranean civilization destroyed by force”, this culture’s emblems being:

“una altísima inspiración y libertad espirituales: una sociedad que tuvo en cuenta el intellectus amoris, el entendimiento del amor y la potencia mediadora de la lengua” (Rivera, 2005, p. 110).

“A towering spiritual inspiration and freedom: a society that took into account the intellectus amoris, love’s understanding, and language’s mediating potential” (Rivera, 2005, p.110).

This consequential spiritual crisis in the West has been commented by Gilbert Durand, French anthropologist, who has thoroughly studied the history of symbolic thinking in Western culture. Alain Verjat, who closely studies Durand’s work, observes that the latter shows that said crisis is due to the fact that “occidente apostó (y desgraciadamente ganó) por el racionalismo y el cartesianismo, de los que el método científico es el producto directo, tanto en las ciencias ‘exactas’ como en las ciencias ‘humanas’” (Verjat, 2011, p.19) (“the West bet for (and unfortunately it won) Rationalism and Cartesianism –its direct product being the scientific method– both in ‘exact’ sciences and ‘human’ sciences”). This event unfolds ever since, in Western history, Aristotelian conceptualism, i.e., “el pensamiento directo, que se funda en el realismo de la percepción” (Verjat, 2011, p.19) (“direct thought, which emerges from the realism of perception”), oriented towards objective knowledge “de las realidades del mundo profano y del dominio de la naturaleza” (Verjat, 2011, p.19) (“of the realities of the profane world and the domination of nature”), overcame Platonism in the symbolic thought that supported an indirect thinking that could “designar algo más allá de los sensible” (Verjat, 2011, p.19) (“design something beyond the perceptible”). This is a fact we mentioned earlier from the perspective of the theory of the polarity of the sexes, which implied, too, the defense of one of the intellects’ legitimacy (intellectus rationis). This crisis, then, lays its foundations ever since only one path to knowledge is recognized as valid, while symbolism became increasingly discredited in philosophy, “de tal modo que el Siglo de las Luces pudo proclamar el triunfo de la razón, relegando todo lo que no fuera racional al desván de las supersticiones” (Verjat, 2011, p.19) (“so that the Age of Enlightenment could claim the triumph of reason, relegating anything but what is rational to the attic of superstitions”).

Returning to the authors’ approaches: the troubadour culture, their visions on love, and their spiritual freedom and richness, persecuted through the Crusades against Albigensian (Rivera, 2005, p.107) are longed by Simone Weil, as María Zambrano looks forward to a reconciliation between philosophy and poetry, while Virginia Woolf looks for synthesis and complementarity both intellectual and sexual through androgyny, which is proposed as one of Woolf’s solution to gender-sex oppression against women – which is not the only one[11]. That is to say, each of these authors perceive, in one way or another, “una pérdida insoportable de libertad humana en la historia” (Rivera, 2005, p. 109) (“an unbearable loss of human liberty in history”). Further, it is important to consider that all of them wrote amidst crisis in their corresponding territories (two World Wars and, in Weil and Zambrano’s cases, the Spanish Civil War), and that they were intensely related to war. So they wrote in a moment when questioning about how they got to such a critical point led them through similar paths of thoughts. Thus, our intention is to point out the need to build a philosophy that does not deny otherness[12], the affections, or (transcendental) knowledge that is not mediated by reason. This is a reflection that has taken quite an important place within feminine thought, both past –as we saw in Marguerite Porete, and other Beguines and mystic women– and current, as Zambrano, Woolf, and Weil’s contributions have shown.

Declaration of Conflicts of Interests
The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest.

Notes

[1]It’s worth mentioning that the protagonist’s building as allegoric characters is a clear reference to Medieval Courtly Literature, specifically from Jean Meung and Guillaume de Lorris’ Román de la Rose.

[2] A place that is both a “un modo de ser y un estado” (Garí, 1995, p. 54) (“way to be and a state”) where mystic experience takes place, crucially marked by the renunciation of the will and the annihilation of the soul.

[3] All the quotes in this article that required translation to English have been translated by Catalina Soto Caballero and edited by Yennadim Medina Reales.

[4] This characterization of Love as the highest possible form of understanding for the Soul, along with the insufficiency and abandonment of Reason, is a theme that was “común a buena parte de la mística femenina del siglo XIII y XIV” (Garí, 1995, p. 63) (“common to a large part of 13th-14th centuries Female Mysticism”), and therefore, quite frequent in the emerging “Teología Vernácula” (Durán, 2021, p. 1) (“Vernacular Theology”) of the 12th century. It is important to highlight that Marguerite Porete’s writing is framed within a major feminine spiritual movement that crystallised in Western territories since 1200 (Cirlot & Garí, 1999, p.17), where, besides the novelty about a group of women taking hold of writing for the first time, new currents of feminine spirituality and new religious movements led by women emerged such as, for example, Cathars, nuns, recluses, and beguines. Marguerite Porete belonged in the last group: the mulieres religiosae.   

[5]What’s more, the problem of love and reason as two fundamental human capabilities, along with whether they complement or compenetrate each other, possess a long trajectory in Medieval thought. As pointed out by Meis in her article, “Razón y amor en la teología medieval incipiente: Aproximación desde la confluencia de las fuentes griegas y latinas” (2002) (“Reason and Love in Early Medieval Theology: An approach from the Confluence of Greek and Latin Sources”), theological development of authors such as Hildegard von Bingen, William of St. Thierry, Anselm of Canterbury, and Bonaventure –among others– underscores, in different ways, the importance of the collaboration between both human capabilities (love and reason) in the search for Truth and, thence, God.

[6] The complementarity of the sexes Theory establishes that men and women are substantially different, but equal in worth. Active mostly during the 12th and 13th centuries, this thought implies that both men and women complemented humanity, that is to say, we belonged to the same species. According to María-Milagros Rivera, this Theory was “efecto y causa de mucha libertad en la vida de las mujeres” (Rivera, 2005, p-96) (“effect and cause of too much freedom in women’s life”). Contrary to this one is the polarity of the sexes theory, which has its origins with Aristotle. This Theory poses that both men and women are substantially different and that men are superior to women. This thought was mainly spread by the Church and Universities through the thirteenth century (Rivera, 2005, p. 98).

[7] Considering that in the 12th century proliferation of secular and heretic spiritual groups had already begun – paradoxically at the same time the clergy’s authority and power was in the process of consolidation (Walker Bynum, 1984, p.19) – medievalist Caroline Walker Bynum affirms that beguines (group to which Marguerite Porete belonged to) were, probably, “the first ‘women’s movement’ in Western history” (Walker Bynum, 1984, p.14). At the same time, she points out that after the year 1200, mystic women were already more numerous than mystic males (Walker Bynum, 1984, p.18), that is to say, she observes a rise in spiritual and religious participation of medieval women.

[8] In this sense, the mystic tradition in itself questioned Reason as a means to God’s knowledge, the “Biblical interpretation… based on rational, philosophical and theological arguments” (Lerner, 1993, p.65), by stating that “transcendent knowledge came not as a product of rational thought, but as a result of a way of life, of individual inspiration and sudden revelatory insight” (Lerner, 1993, p.66), and that “mystics saw human beings, the world and the universe· in a state of relatedness, open to understanding by intuitive and immediate perception. Its practitioners saw God as immanent in all of creation, accessible through unconditional love and concentrated dedication manifested in sincere prayer and religious devotion” (Lerner, 1993, p.66). Women, who did not have access to elite education as theologians, in spite of remaining excluded from this knowledge, used mysticism “as an alternate mode of thought to patriarchal thinking” (Lerner, 1993, p.77).

[9] Mystic women were not the exception. Just like Rivera, Tomassi and Weil propose from diverse perspectives, the relevance of intellectus amoris was defended by both male and female troubadours, Cathars and Albigenses, as well as by the “knightly Civilization” that emerged in Provence and was expressed in Occitan language.

[10] It is important to highlight that many of the beguines have been inspired by courtly poetry, and because of this, finding expressions of this style is not an aspect exclusive to Porete. As it is mentioned in the introduction to the text El lenguaje del deseo [The Language of Desire] (1999), many writings by beguines are marked by, first, the use of vernacular languages or mother tongues to “expresar sus experiencias… para cantar sus exigencias apasionada del amor” (Hadewijch, 1999, p.39) (“express their experiences… to sing their hot-blooded demands of love”), a matter that ends up emancipating those languages. Second, the inspiration of Courtly Poetry. And thirdly, the renovation of spirituality. These three elements allow that beguines’ writings, such as those by Hadewijch of Ambers, Marguerite Porete, and Mechthild of Magdeburg, become an exceptional contribution that “se encuentran, junto a trovadoras, trovadores y autores de las canciones de gesta, en el origen de las grandes literaturas europeas” (Hadewijch, 1999, p.39) (“can be found, along with both female and male troubadours and chanson the gests’ authors, at the origin of the great European literature”).

[11] Not the only one, since androgyny posed by Woolf. A Room of One’s Own last chapter is just one of the feminist proposals of the essay. In the rest of the chapters, in tune with difference feminism or “social feminism” (Marcus, 2010, p.145), Woolf’s approach reaffirms the category “women” and its consequent “difference”, based “on the belief that women’s values and skills, whether innate or culturally constructed, are excluded in male-dominated societies”. In this way, in a “complex and often contradictory” synthesis (Marcus, 2010, p.144), Virginia “calls for a new understanding a valorisation of specifically female values” (Marcus, 2010, p.145) –in a vindication of female difference– as well as she points towards a dilution of the same category “women” through androgyny and the necessary sexual complementarity of the sexes.  De este modo, en una síntesis “complex and often contradictory” (Marcus, 2010, p.144), Virginia tanto “calls for a new understanding and valorisation of specifically female values” (Marcus, 2010, p.145), en una reafirmación de la diferencia femenina, como apunta también a una dilución de la categoría “mujer” a través de la propuesta de la androginia y la necesaria complementariedad sexual de los intelectos.

[12] Just as Gilbert Durand tried in Science de L’Homme Et Tradition (1975), after understanding that throughout history many thinkers that did not fit in the dominant Western philosophy’s principles were excluded. Thus, Durand “expresa la necesidad de escribir una historia de la «antifilosofía», de rescatar a «todos los “rechazados” por el pensamiento occidental oficial»” (Hadewijch, 1999, p.34) (“expresses the need to write a history of ‘anti-philosophy’, to rescue «all of the ‘rejected’ by the official Western thought»”), and  so he makes an extensive list where he names those forgotten men (“the others”) from the Middle Ages to present times- However, Durand’s complaint also seems to reproduce otherness and marginalization since it does not include any woman, as pointed out by María Tabuyo in El lenguaje del deseo (Hadewijch, 1999, p.34-35).

References

Cirlot, V., & Garí, B. (1999). El anonadamiento del alma en Margarita Porete. En Cirlot, V. y Garí, B., La mirada interior: escritoras místicas y visionarias en la Edad Media (pp. 223-253). Ediciones Martínez Roca.

Cirlot, V., & Garí, B. (2021). 8 mujeres: sus vidas y su obra. En Cirlot, V. y Garí, B., La mirada interior: escritoras místicas y visionarias en la Edad Media (pp. 15-48). Siruela.

Cirlot, V., & Garí, B. (2021). Itinerarios espirituales: escaleras, caleidoscopios y la mística del descenso. En Cirlot, V. y Garí, B., La mirada interior: escritoras místicas y visionarias en la Edad Media (pp. 316-330). Siruela.

Corral, E. (2018). Mística y amor cortés. En C. Cuadrada (Ed.), Voces de Mujeres En La Edad Media: Entre Realidad Y Ficción (pp. 309-320). Walter de Gruyter GmbH.

De Lorris, G., y De Meung, J. (1985). Román de la Rose. Quadems Crema.

Durán, L. (2021). Matilde de Magdeburgo y Margarita Porete. Diferentes modos de comprender el amor en la unión con la divinidad. Síntesis. Revista de Filosofía, 4(1), 1-26.

Durand, G. (1999).Ciencia del hombre y tradición. El nuevo espíritu antropológico. (A. López y M. Tabuyo, Trad.). Paidós.

Garí, B. (1995). El camino al “País de la libertad” en El Espejo de las almas simples. Revista d’Estudis Feministes, 9, 49–68.

Garí, B. (2010). Le plus de l’ame. María Zambrano y la mística de la Edad Media. Revista Aurora, 11, 56-62.

Garí, B. (2005). Introducción. En M. Porete. El espejo de las almas simples (pp. 9-33). Siruela.

Lerner, Gerda. (1993). The Way of the Mystics-1. The Creation of Feminist Consciousness (pp. 65- 87). Oxford University Press.

Marcus, L. (2010) Woolf’s feminism and feminism’s Woolf. En S. Sellers (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Virginia Woolf (pp. 142 –179). Cambridge University Press.

Meis, A. (2002). Razón y amor en la teología medieval incipiente: Aproximación desde la confluencia de las fuentes griegas y latinas. Teología y vida43(4), 541-579.

Porete, M (2005). El espejo de las almas simples (B. Garí, Trad.). Siruela.

Porete, M. (2015). El espejo de las almas simples (B. Garí, Trad.). Siruela.

Rivera, M.-M. (2005). La diferencia sexual en la historia. (1a ed.). Universitat de València.

Hadewijch. de A. (1999). El lenguaje del deseo: poemas de Hadewijch de Amberes. Trotta.

Tomassi, W. (2002). Filósofos y mujeres (C. Ballester Maseguer, Trad.). Narcea.

Verjat, A. (2011). Presentación. En Gilbert D., La crisis espiritual en Occidente. Las confesiones de Eranos (pp. 9-27). Ediciones Siruela.

Walker Bynum, C. (1984).  Jesus as a mother. University of California Press.

Weil, S. (1960). Écrits historiques et politiques. Gallimard.

Woolf, V. (2010). Un cuarto propio. Cuarto propio.

Zambrano, M. (2019). Claros del bosque. Alianza Editorial.

Zambrano, M. (1993). Filosofía y poesía. Fondo de cultura económica.

Javiera Steck Navarrete. BA in Hispanic Literature and Linguistics from Universidad de Chile. Teacher Assistant of Literary Theory (Universidad O’Higgins), Introduction to Literary Theory (Universidad de Chile). Has been collaborator in the latinoamerican culture and politics magazine La Raza Cómica and Palabra Pública magazine from Universidad de Chile. Javiera belongs to the program P.I.A., “Programa Interestudiantil Autogestionado” (Self-managed Inter-student Program) of Linguistics and Hispanic Literature, and the women’s outreach and research project “Revista Elena”. Her major interests areas are Latin American Literature, Feminist Theory, and Female Medieval Mystic.

Josefa Vecchiola Gallego. BA in Hispanic Literature and Linguistics from Universidad de Chile. Josefa belongs to the program P.I.A., “Programa Interestudiantil Autogestionado” (Self-managed Inter-student Program) of Hispanic Literature and Linguistics. Her major interest areas are Chilean Contemporary Literature, Female Medieval Mysticism, and Education.

The ten kinds of conditionals and Chrysippus’ criterion

/
239 views

Miguel López-Astorga

Institute of Humanistic Studies “Juan Ignacio Molina”, University of Talca, Talca Campus (Chile). ORCID ID: 0000-0002-6004-0587. Email address: milopez@utalca.cl

 Volume 13, Number 2, 2021 I Full-Text PDF

DOI: 10.21659/rupkatha.v13n2.52

Abstract:

The theory of mental models proposed ten possible interpretations for the conditional. In particular, Johnson-Laird and Byrne provided those interpretations in 2002. On the other hand, in ancient times, Chrysippus of Soli claimed that conditionals have to fulfill a requirement: the negation of their consequents must be inconsistent with their antecedents. This paper considers the ten interpretations of the conditional the theory of mental models indicates as ten different kinds of conditionals. Thus, it analyzes those ten types from Chrysippus’ requirement. The results show that the ten kinds of conditionals that can be derived from the theses of the theory of mental models follow the criterion given by Chrysippus. Accordingly, it can be thought that the criterion refers to an essential characteristic of the conditional.

Keywords: Chrysippus’ criterion, conditional, possibility, state-description, theory of mental models